Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen steering paradox “2=1” for N qubits
Abstract
Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) paradox highlights the absence of a local realistic explanation for quantum mechanics, and shows the incompatibility of the local-hidden-state models with quantum theory. For N-qubit states, or more importantly, the N-qubit mixed states, we present the EPR steering paradox in the form of the contradictory equality “2=1”. We show that the contradiction holds for any N-qubit state as long as both “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement” are satisfied. This also indicates that the EPR steering paradox exists in more general cases. Finally, we give specific examples to demonstrate and analyze our arguments.
1. Introduction
The quantum paradox serves as a powerful tool in elucidating the fundamental distinction between the quantum theory and the classical theory. Quantum correlations play a central role in the study of quantum information and quantum mechanics. Among the quantum correlations, quantum entanglement and Bell’s nonlocality are the first to be proposed and studied. In 1935, Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR) published their famous article “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?”,1 which questioned the completeness of quantum mechanics under the assumptions of locality and reality. This is nowadays well known as the EPR paradox. Soon after the publication of the EPR paper, Schrödinger introduced two important concepts, namely, quantum entanglement and quantum steering.2,3 Quantum entanglement distinguishes quantum theory from classical theory. Quantum steering is closely related to “the spooky action at a distance”. However, the idea of steering did not receive considerable attention or advancement until the year 2007, at which point Wiseman et al. presented a meticulous definition by utilizing quantum information concepts.4,5 So far, quantum steering has been widely applied in various fields.6,7,8,9
Steering is a quantum correlation between entanglement10 and Bell nonlocality.11,12,13 Steering is used to describe the situation in a bipartite system. When people use different observables to detect one of the particles, it will cause the corresponding other particle to collapse to a certain state. In practice, Alice prepares a bipartite quantum state, and she sends one of the particles to Bob. They each measure the particles in their hands and communicate over a classical channel. It is Alice’s task to convince Bob that Alice has prepared a pair of entangled state. In the process, Bob needs to assess the correctness of the assumptions of quantum mechanics and acknowledge the measurements as described by quantum mechanics. Specifically, Bob can disbelieve Alice’s equipment and measurements. However, in this case, Bob needs to rule out the influence of hidden variables on the measurement results by the measurements he has in hand. Bob can fully trust his own equipment and results. If Bob cannot explain the measurement results on his side with the local-hidden states (LHS), he must recognize that Alice has prepared an entangled bipartite state. Only EPR steering states can accomplish this task. Quantum steering is an asymmetric quantum nonlocality. That is, in some cases Alice can steer Bob, but in turn Bob cannot steer Alice.14,15,16,17,18 Based on some properties of quantum steering, Chen et al. proposed the EPR steering paradox “2=1”,19 where “2” is the quantum result and “1” is the corresponding result of LHS models. They verified the EPR steering state by the contradiction between quantum mechanics and classical theory. In the 2-setting EPR steering protocol, they found that any 2-qubit entangled pure state possesses the contradiction. Thereafter, Liu et al. found that such a contradiction was also valid for a specific 4-qubit entangled mixed state.20 In other words, the discussion of the EPR steering paradox “2=1” has been limited to arbitrary 2-qubit pure state and a special 4-qubit mixed state.
The purpose of this paper is to study the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N qubits. Based on the 2-setting steering protocol, we have obtained such EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N-qubit entangled states. In this work, we demonstrate that any N-qubit state can lead to the contradiction, provided that both “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement” are fulfilled simultaneously. This paper is organized as follows. In Sec. 2, we propose a theorem for N-qubit quantum states that contains two requirements: “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”. In Sec. 3, we obtain the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for the N-qubit states under Bell-like basis measurement. In Sec. 4, we apply the results to the 2-qubit mixed states and obtain a corollary that there is no EPR steering paradox “2=1” for 2-qubit mixed states. Finally, we conclude with a summary in Sec. 5. Some detailed proofs are given in Appendix A, B, and C.
2. EPR Steering Paradox “2=1” for N-Qubit States
2.1. “2=1” for the 2-qubit pure state and the 4-qubit mixed state
To make the paper be self-contained, in this subsection let us make a brief review. In 2016, Chen et al. first simplified the EPR steering paradox as a contradiction “2=1” for any 2-qubit pure entangled state.19 They analyzed a 2-qubit pure entangled state given by
If Bob’s states have an LHS description, then there exists an ensemble {℘ξρξ} and a stochastic map ℘(a|ˆn,ξ) satisfying
Then Bob’s four unnormalized conditional states satisfy Eq. (5), and one has
After that, in 2021, Liu et al. found a 4-qubit mixed entangled state
If Bob’s states have an LHS description, they must satisfy Eqs. (5) and (6). Because the eight states of Eq. (16) are pure states, it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 8. A pure state cannot be obtained by convex combination of other pure states, one has
2.2. “2=1” for N-qubit states
In this subsection, we study the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N-qubit states. Our result is the following theorem.
Theorem 1. In the 2-setting steering protocol {ˆn1,ˆn2}, Alice and Bob share an N-qubit state ρAB. Assume that Alice measures along ˆn1 and ˆn2, and then Bob obtains ˜ρˆn1a and ˜ρˆn2a′, respectively, where a,a′ is the measurement result of Alice. There will be a contradiction of “2=1” if ρAB satisfies simultaneously “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”. The two requirements are
(1) | The pure state requirement: Bob’s unnormalized conditional states {˜ρˆn1a} and {˜ρˆn2a′} are all pure states. | ||||
(2) | The measurement requirement: any one of {˜ρˆn1a} is different from any one of {˜ρˆn2a′}. |
Let Alice and Bob share an N-qubit entangled state
The two requirements can be rewritten as
(1) | The pure state requirement:|η(α)i±〉and|ε(α)j±〉are independent ofα. | ||||
(2) | The measurement requirement: for the result obtained by Bob, any one of{|ηi±〉}is different from any one of{|εj±〉}. |
The pure state requirement guarantees that Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are all pure states. After Alice’s measurement, Bob obtains the states
The measurement requirement suggests that if Alice chooses different measurements ˆPˆn1a or ˆPˆn2a′, Bob cannot get the same result. We prove that in Appendix A and Appendix B the results obtained by Bob cannot be the same in different measurements. “The different measurements” refer to the measurements in different directions (ˆn1 and ˆn2). After Alice’s measurements, Bob obtains s(α)i±|η(α)i±〉 and |χ(α)j±〉=∑iV(j±)(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±〉. It can be seen that |χ(α)j±〉 is obtained by superposition of |η(α)i±〉. If Bob’s two results are required to be different, |χ(α)j±〉 contains at least two summation terms. This also requires: (1) At least two terms in the summation in |ψ(α)AB〉 are nonzero. That is, at least two s(α)i± in |ψ(α)AB〉 are nonzero. (2) The matrix {V(j±)(i±)} has at least two nonzero matrix elements in each row. That is, the two measurements Pˆn1a and Pˆn2a′ are different. (3) |ψ(α)AB〉≠[∑i(s(α)i+|+ϕi〉+s(α)i−|−ϕi〉)]⊗|η(α)ℓ〉, where |η(α)ℓ〉 is one of {|η(α)i±〉} That is, each |ψ(α)AB〉 is an entangled state.
Proof. Here, we prove that for N-qubit state ρAB, the difference between quantum theory and classical theory can be expressed as “2=1”, as long as the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied. It is well known that if ρAB satisfies two requirements at the same time, Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are all pure states. And for different measurements ˆPˆn1a and ˆPˆn2a′, Bob’s results are different. Without loss of generality, we assume that Bob’s 2M+1 unnormalized conditional states are different. Then for the quantum results, we have
Suppose Bob’s states have an LHS description, they must satisfy Eqs. (5) and (6). Then, Bob will check the following set of 2M+1 equations :
In the quantum result, there are pure states in Eq. (31). Then in the LHS description, it is sufficient to take from 1 to . It is a fact that a density matrix of pure state can only be expanded by itself. Therefore, any in Eq. (32) contains only one term. So for the LHS models results, we have
Remark 1. For 2-qubit pure state Eq. (2), Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are always pure. So we only need to verify whether it satisfies the measurement requirement. It can be seen that in the 2-setting protocol , Bob’s results are and , respectively.19 Obviously, this satisfies the measurement requirement. According to our analysis, such state equation (2) can get the contradiction “”.
Remark 2. For the 4-qubit mixed state Eq. (12), it is necessary to analyze whether it satisfies both the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement. In the 2-setting protocol , Bob’s eight conditional states are all pure states as shown in Eq. (16). For two different measurements and , Bob’s results are different. It is obvious that the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied at the same time, so the specific 4-qubit mixed state equation (12) can also get the contradiction “”.
In the EPR steering paradox, we propose a theorem for N-qubit quantum states which contains two requirements: the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement. If Alice and Bob share an N-qubit mixed state, there will be a contradiction of “” only when the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied at the same time. If they share an N-qubit pure state, the pure state requirement is automatically satisfied. In this situation, after Alice’s measurement, Bob must get a pure state, which only needs to meet the measurement requirement. Our results are completely consistent with the previous conclusions. This confirms the correctness of our conclusion.
3. Bell-Like Basis Measurement
Here we show a more specific example of the Bell-like basis measurement for the N-qubit mixed states. Let us consider Alice and Bob share an N-qubit entangled state , in which may be written as
The Bell-like basis measurement can be written as
First, in Bell-like basis measurement, the transformation matrix is
It is apparent that after a series of analysis, the form of is simple and only contains two terms. There is an interesting question worthy of our further analysis, that is, whether and can contain the same states? Suppose that and are
Therefore, for arbitrary and , we have
In summary, we discuss the steering paradox with the Bell-like basis measurement. It shows that for Bell-like basis measurement, when satisfied both the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement, we can obtain the contradiction “”. In this case, and cannot contain the same state, and only contain two items. It is evident that the maximum value range of is from 1 to (M is the number of particles of Alice), that is, the maximum rank of is for the Bell-like basis measurement.
4. Nonexistence of Contradiction “” for 2-Qubit Mixed States
In this section, we apply the results to the 2-qubit mixed states. We get the following corollary.
Corollary 1. If Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit mixed state, there is no contradiction “”.
From the above analysis, we know that for the Bell-like basis measurement, the maximum rank of is . Suppose Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit entangled state and each of them has a qubit, then . If Alice performs the Bell-like basis measurement, the maximum rank of is 1. That is, for 2-qubit entangled states with the Bell-like basis measurement, only the 2-qubit prue entangled states have the contradiction “”. So is there a contradiction “” for 2-qubit mixed states? Next, we prove that there is no contradiction “” for 2-qubit mixed states
Proof. Suppose Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit mixed state , in which
5. Conclusion
We have presented a simple EPR steering paradox that shows the incompatibility of the local-hidden-state models with quantum theory for any N-qubit entangled state based on a 2-setting steering protocol. The argument is valid for any N-qubit entangled state, not only N-qubit pure entangled states, but more importantly, N-qubit mixed entangled states. We propose a simple theorem and prove that for any N-qubit state satisfying simultaneously “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”, then the contradiction “” can be obtained. In the example of Bell-like basis measurement, we obtain that the maximum rank of the N-qubit mixed state is (M is the number of particles of Alice), and prove that there is no contradiction “” in the 2-qubit mixed state. In general, we obtain the contradiction “” in a more general case. Furthermore, if one considers the EPR steering scenario in k-setting for arbitrary N-qudit entangled mixed state, then following the similar approach, one can arrive at a full contradiction, i.e. “”.
Acknowledgments
J.L.C. is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant Nos. 12275136 and 12075001) and the 111 Project of B23045. H.X.M. is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant No. 11901317). Z.J.L. is supported by the Nankai Zhide Foundation.
ORCID
Zhi-Jie Liu https://orcid.org/0009-0008-0373-1796
Jie Zhou https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7518-3716
Hui-Xian Meng https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3807-7201
Xing-Yan Fan https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0702-4094
Mi Xie https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2482-121X
Fu-Lin Zhang https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7077-1001
Jing-Ling Chen https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3411-6015
Appendix A. Can Bob Have the Same State in the Same Measurement?
In order to obtain the contradiction “”, we analyze whether Bob can have the same pure state in the same measurement, and whether Bob can have the same pure state in different measurements.
After Alice’s measurement, Bob obtains
In Eq. (A.1), assuming that , i.e. only different pure states appear in the quantum result of Eq. (A.1), so that it is sufficient to take from 1 to , namely, one can take the ensemble as
Because , one has
Appendix B. Can Bob Have the Same State in Different Measurements?
In Eq. (A.1), assuming that , i.e. only different pure states appear in the quantum result of Eq. (A.1). Similarly, it is sufficient to take from 1 to , one can take the ensemble as Eq. (A.2). Then one has Eq. (A.3). The states on the left-hand side of Eq. (A.1) are all pure states. The same reasoning can be used to obtain
Because , one has
Appendix C. is a Set of Complete Basis of Hilbert Space
Here we show that () which in the Bell-like basis measurement is a set of complete basis of -dimensional Hilbert space. For any k(), we have . That can be expanded as