Processing math: 44%
World Scientific
Skip main navigation

Cookies Notification

We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experience. By continuing to browse the site, you consent to the use of our cookies. Learn More
×

System Upgrade on Tue, May 28th, 2024 at 2am (EDT)

Existing users will be able to log into the site and access content. However, E-commerce and registration of new users may not be available for up to 12 hours.
For online purchase, please visit us again. Contact us at customercare@wspc.com for any enquiries.

Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen steering paradox “2=1” for N qubits

    https://doi.org/10.1142/S0217732324500305Cited by:2 (Source: Crossref)

    Abstract

    Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) paradox highlights the absence of a local realistic explanation for quantum mechanics, and shows the incompatibility of the local-hidden-state models with quantum theory. For N-qubit states, or more importantly, the N-qubit mixed states, we present the EPR steering paradox in the form of the contradictory equality “2=1”. We show that the contradiction holds for any N-qubit state as long as both “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement” are satisfied. This also indicates that the EPR steering paradox exists in more general cases. Finally, we give specific examples to demonstrate and analyze our arguments.

    1. Introduction

    The quantum paradox serves as a powerful tool in elucidating the fundamental distinction between the quantum theory and the classical theory. Quantum correlations play a central role in the study of quantum information and quantum mechanics. Among the quantum correlations, quantum entanglement and Bell’s nonlocality are the first to be proposed and studied. In 1935, Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR) published their famous article “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?”,1 which questioned the completeness of quantum mechanics under the assumptions of locality and reality. This is nowadays well known as the EPR paradox. Soon after the publication of the EPR paper, Schrödinger introduced two important concepts, namely, quantum entanglement and quantum steering.2,3 Quantum entanglement distinguishes quantum theory from classical theory. Quantum steering is closely related to “the spooky action at a distance”. However, the idea of steering did not receive considerable attention or advancement until the year 2007, at which point Wiseman et al. presented a meticulous definition by utilizing quantum information concepts.4,5 So far, quantum steering has been widely applied in various fields.6,7,8,9

    Steering is a quantum correlation between entanglement10 and Bell nonlocality.11,12,13 Steering is used to describe the situation in a bipartite system. When people use different observables to detect one of the particles, it will cause the corresponding other particle to collapse to a certain state. In practice, Alice prepares a bipartite quantum state, and she sends one of the particles to Bob. They each measure the particles in their hands and communicate over a classical channel. It is Alice’s task to convince Bob that Alice has prepared a pair of entangled state. In the process, Bob needs to assess the correctness of the assumptions of quantum mechanics and acknowledge the measurements as described by quantum mechanics. Specifically, Bob can disbelieve Alice’s equipment and measurements. However, in this case, Bob needs to rule out the influence of hidden variables on the measurement results by the measurements he has in hand. Bob can fully trust his own equipment and results. If Bob cannot explain the measurement results on his side with the local-hidden states (LHS), he must recognize that Alice has prepared an entangled bipartite state. Only EPR steering states can accomplish this task. Quantum steering is an asymmetric quantum nonlocality. That is, in some cases Alice can steer Bob, but in turn Bob cannot steer Alice.14,15,16,17,18 Based on some properties of quantum steering, Chen et al. proposed the EPR steering paradox “2=1”,19 where “2” is the quantum result and “1” is the corresponding result of LHS models. They verified the EPR steering state by the contradiction between quantum mechanics and classical theory. In the 2-setting EPR steering protocol, they found that any 2-qubit entangled pure state possesses the contradiction. Thereafter, Liu et al. found that such a contradiction was also valid for a specific 4-qubit entangled mixed state.20 In other words, the discussion of the EPR steering paradox “2=1” has been limited to arbitrary 2-qubit pure state and a special 4-qubit mixed state.

    The purpose of this paper is to study the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N qubits. Based on the 2-setting steering protocol, we have obtained such EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N-qubit entangled states. In this work, we demonstrate that any N-qubit state can lead to the contradiction, provided that both “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement” are fulfilled simultaneously. This paper is organized as follows. In Sec. 2, we propose a theorem for N-qubit quantum states that contains two requirements: “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”. In Sec. 3, we obtain the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for the N-qubit states under Bell-like basis measurement. In Sec. 4, we apply the results to the 2-qubit mixed states and obtain a corollary that there is no EPR steering paradox “2=1” for 2-qubit mixed states. Finally, we conclude with a summary in Sec. 5. Some detailed proofs are given in Appendix A, B, and C.

    2. EPR Steering Paradox “2=1” for N-Qubit States

    2.1. “2=1” for the 2-qubit pure state and the 4-qubit mixed state

    To make the paper be self-contained, in this subsection let us make a brief review. In 2016, Chen et al. first simplified the EPR steering paradox as a contradiction “2=1” for any 2-qubit pure entangled state.19 They analyzed a 2-qubit pure entangled state given by

    ρAB=|Ψ(θ)Ψ(θ)|,(1)
    where
    |Ψ(θ)=cosθ|0|0+sinθ|1|1,(2)
    with θ(0,π2). They chose the 2-setting protocol as {,ˆx}. In the protocol, Bob asks Alice to carry out either one of two possible projective measurements on her qubit along the z-direction and the x-direction, i.e.
    P0=|00|,P1=|11|,Pˆx0=|++|,Pˆx1=||,(3)
    where |±=(12)(|0±|1), and to inform him of the measurement results of “a” (where a=0,1). Then Bob’s four unnormalized conditional states are
    ˜ρ0=cos2θ|00|,˜ρ1=sin2θ|11|,˜ρˆx0=12(cosθ|0+sinθ|1)(cosθ0|+sinθ1|),˜ρˆx1=12(cosθ|0sinθ|1)(cosθ0|sinθ1|).(4)

    If Bob’s states have an LHS description, then there exists an ensemble {ξρξ} and a stochastic map (a|ˆn,ξ) satisfying

    ˜ρˆna=ξ(a|ˆn,ξ)ξρξ(5)
    and
    ξξρξ=ρB.(6)
    Here ξ and (a|ˆn,ξ) are probabilities satisfying
    ξξ=1(7)
    and
    a(a|ˆn,ξ)=1,(8)
    for a fixed ξ, and ρB=trA(ρAB) is Bob’s reduced density matrix.4,5

    Then Bob’s four unnormalized conditional states satisfy Eq. (5), and one has

    ˜ρ0=ξ(0|,ξ)ξρξ,˜ρ1=ξ(1|,ξ)ξρξ,˜ρˆx0=ξ(0|ˆx,ξ)ξρξ,˜ρˆx1=ξ(1|ˆx,ξ)ξρξ.(9)
    Because the four states of Eq. (4) are pure states, it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 4. Equation (9) can be written as
    ˜ρ0=(0|,1)1ρ1+(0|,2)2ρ2+(0|,3)3ρ3+(0|,4)4ρ4,˜ρ1=(1|,1)1ρ1+(1|,2)2ρ2+(1|,3)3ρ3+(1|,4)4ρ4,˜ρˆx0=(0|ˆx,1)1ρ1+(0|ˆx,2)2ρ2+(0|ˆx,3)3ρ3+(0|ˆx,4)4ρ4,˜ρˆx1=(1|ˆx,1)1ρ1+(1|ˆx,2)2ρ2+(1|ˆx,3)3ρ3+(1|ˆx,4)4ρ4.(10)
    Owing to the fact that a pure state cannot be obtained by convex combination of other pure states, one has
    ˜ρ0=1ρ1,˜ρ1=2ρ2,˜ρˆx0=3ρ3,˜ρˆx1=4ρ4.(11)
    Here
    (0|,1)=(1|,2)=(0|ˆx,3)=(1|ˆx,4)=1,
    and other (a|ˆn,ξ)=0. By summing four terms up in Eq. (11) and taking trace, the left side gives tr(˜ρ+˜ρˆx)=2tr(ρB)=2. But the right side gives tr(1ρ1+2ρ2+3ρ3+4ρ4)=tr(ρB)=1, then one can obtain the contradiction “2=1”, i.e. the EPR steering paradox, for any 2-qubit pure entangled state.

    After that, in 2021, Liu et al. found a 4-qubit mixed entangled state

    ρ(θ)=cos2θ|LC4LC4|+sin2θ|LC4LC4|,(12)
    where
    |LC4=12(|0000+|1100+|0011|1111),|LC4=12(|0100+|1000+|0111|1011),(13)
    are the linear cluster states.20 Alice prepares the state ρ(θ) as in Eq. (12). She keeps 1,2 particles and sends 3,4 particles to Bob. In the 2-setting steering protocol {ˆn1,ˆn2}(ˆn1ˆn2), with
    ˆn1=σzσzzz,ˆn2=σyσxyx.(14)
    In the protocol, Bob asks Alice to carry out either one of two possible projective measurements on her qubits, i.e.
    Pˆn100=|0000|,Pˆn101=|0101|,Pˆn110=|1010|,Pˆn111=|1111|,Pˆn200=|++|,Pˆn201=||,Pˆn210=|++|,Pˆn211=||,(15)
    where |±=(12)(|0±|1), |=(12)(|0±i|1). After Alice’s measurement, Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are
    ˜ρˆn100=14cos2θ(|00+|11)(00|+11|),˜ρˆn101=14sin2θ(|00+|11)(00|+11|),˜ρˆn110=14sin2θ(|00|11)(00|11|),˜ρˆn111=14cos2θ(|00|11)(00|11|),˜ρˆn200=18(|00+i|11)(00|i11|),˜ρˆn201=18(|00i|11)(00|+i11|),˜ρˆn210=18(|00i|11)(00|+i11|),˜ρˆn211=18(|00+i|11)(00|i11|).(16)

    If Bob’s states have an LHS description, they must satisfy Eqs. (5) and (6). Because the eight states of Eq. (16) are pure states, it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 8. A pure state cannot be obtained by convex combination of other pure states, one has

    ˜ρˆn100=1ρ1,˜ρˆn101=2ρ2,˜ρˆn110=3ρ3,˜ρˆn111=4ρ4,˜ρˆn200=5ρ5,˜ρˆn201=6ρ6,˜ρˆn210=7ρ7,˜ρˆn211=8ρ8.(17)
    By summing eight terms up in Eq. (17) and taking trace, the left side gives tr(˜ρˆn1+˜ρˆn2)=2tr(ρB)=2. But the right side gives tr(8ξ=1ξρξ)=tr(ρB)=1, then one can obtained an EPR steering paradox “2=1” for the specific 4-qubit mixed entangled state.

    2.2. “2=1” for N-qubit states

    In this subsection, we study the EPR steering paradox “2=1” for N-qubit states. Our result is the following theorem.

    Theorem 1. In the 2-setting steering protocol {ˆn1,ˆn2}, Alice and Bob share an N-qubit state ρAB. Assume that Alice measures along ˆn1 and ˆn2, and then Bob obtains ˜ρˆn1a and ˜ρˆn2a, respectively, where a,a is the measurement result of Alice. There will be a contradiction of2=1if ρAB satisfies simultaneously “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”. The two requirements are

    (1)

    The pure state requirement: Bob’s unnormalized conditional states {˜ρˆn1a} and {˜ρˆn2a} are all pure states.

    (2)

    The measurement requirement: any one of {˜ρˆn1a} is different from any one of {˜ρˆn2a}.

    Let Alice and Bob share an N-qubit entangled state

    ρAB=αpα|ψ(α)ABψ(α)AB|.(18)
    Alice has M(M<N) particles and Bob has (NM) particles. In the 2-setting steering protocol {ˆn1,ˆn2} (with ˆn1ˆn2), Alice performs 2M+1 projective measurements, each of them measuring M particles of Alice. For each projective measurement ˆPˆnka, Bob obtains the corresponding unnormalized state ˜ρˆnka=trA[(Pˆnka𝟙)ρAB], with ˆnk the measurement direction, a the Alice’s measurement result, 𝟙 the 2NM×2NM identity matrix. The wave-function |ψ(α)AB may be written as
    |ψ(α)AB=i(s(α)i+|+ϕi|η(α)i++s(α)i|ϕi|η(α)i),(19)
    or
    |ψ(α)AB=j(t(α)j+|+φj|ε(α)j++t(α)j|φj|ε(α)j),(20)
    where i,j=1,2,,2M1. Equations (19) and (20) are two representations of |ψαAB in different bases. Here |±ϕi and |±φj are the eigenstates of the operator ˆPˆnka(withk=1,2), respectively. And {|±ϕi} and {|±φj} are two sets of complete basis of 2M-dimensional Hilbert space, respectively. At the same time, |±ϕi and |±φj also represent Alice’s particles. |η(α)i± and |ε(α)j± are Bob’s collapsed states (unnormalized), where
    |η(α)i±η(α)i±|=trA[(|±ϕi±ϕi|𝟙)|ψ(α)ABψ(α)AB|](21)
    and
    |ε(α)j±ε(α)j±|=trA[(|±φj±φj|𝟙)|ψ(α)ABψ(α)AB|],(22)
    where 𝟙 is a 2(NM)×2(NM) identity matrix. s(α)i± and t(α)j± are complex numbers satisfying
    i(|s(α)i+|2+|s(α)i|2)=1(23)
    and
    j(|t(α)j+|2+|t(α)j|2)=1.(24)

    The two requirements can be rewritten as

    (1)

    The pure state requirement:|η(α)i±and|ε(α)j±are independent ofα.

    (2)

    The measurement requirement: for the result obtained by Bob, any one of{|ηi±}is different from any one of{|εj±}.

    The pure state requirement guarantees that Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are all pure states. After Alice’s measurement, Bob obtains the states

    ˜ρˆn1ai±=αpα|s(α)i±|2|η(α)i±η(α)i±|(25)
    and
    ˜ρˆn2aj±=αpα|t(α)j±|2|ε(α)j±ε(α)j±|.(26)
    Since pα, |s(α)i±|2 and |t(α)j±|2 are all non-negative, any terms cannot cancel. Bob’s un-normalized conditional states are pure if and only if
    {s(α)i±|η(α)i±=cαα(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±,t(α)j±|ε(α)j±=dαα(j±)t(α)j±|ε(α)j±,(27)
    where cαα(i±) and dαα(j±) are arbitrary complex numbers related to i± and j±, respectively. For convenience, we analyze in the representation with {|±ϕi|ηi±} as basis. The projection of |ψ(α)AB in Eq. (19) onto |±φj is
    ±φj|ψ(α)AB=is(α)i±±φj|±ϕi|η(α)i±iV(j±)(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±,(28)
    where V(j±)(i±)±φj|±ϕi, {V(j±)(i±)} can be written as
    V=(V(1+)(1+)V(1+)(2M1+)V(1+)(1)V(1+)(2M1)V(2M1+)(1+)V(2M1+)(2M1+)V(2M1+)(1)V(2M1+)(2M1)V(1)(1+)V(1)(2M1+)V(1)(1)V(1)(2M1)V(2M1)(1+)V(2M1)(2M1+)V(2M1)(1)V(2M1)(2M1)).
    Then we have
    t(α)j±|ε(α)j±=iV(j±)(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±.(29)
    The pure state requirement equation (27) can be expressed as
    {s(α)i±|η(α)i±=cαα(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±,|χ(α)j±=dαα(j±)|χ(α)j±,(30)
    where |χ(α)j±iV(j±)(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±.

    The measurement requirement suggests that if Alice chooses different measurements ˆPˆn1a or ˆPˆn2a, Bob cannot get the same result. We prove that in Appendix A and Appendix B the results obtained by Bob cannot be the same in different measurements. “The different measurements” refer to the measurements in different directions (ˆn1 and ˆn2). After Alice’s measurements, Bob obtains s(α)i±|η(α)i± and |χ(α)j±=iV(j±)(i±)s(α)i±|η(α)i±. It can be seen that |χ(α)j± is obtained by superposition of |η(α)i±. If Bob’s two results are required to be different, |χ(α)j± contains at least two summation terms. This also requires: (1) At least two terms in the summation in |ψ(α)AB are nonzero. That is, at least two s(α)i± in |ψ(α)AB are nonzero. (2) The matrix {V(j±)(i±)} has at least two nonzero matrix elements in each row. That is, the two measurements Pˆn1a and Pˆn2a are different. (3) |ψ(α)AB[i(s(α)i+|+ϕi+s(α)i|ϕi)]|η(α), where |η(α) is one of {|η(α)i±} That is, each |ψ(α)AB is an entangled state.

    Proof. Here, we prove that for N-qubit state ρAB, the difference between quantum theory and classical theory can be expressed as “2=1”, as long as the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied. It is well known that if ρAB satisfies two requirements at the same time, Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are all pure states. And for different measurements ˆPˆn1a and ˆPˆn2a, Bob’s results are different. Without loss of generality, we assume that Bob’s 2M+1 unnormalized conditional states are different. Then for the quantum results, we have

    {˜ρˆn1a1+=αpα|s(α)1+|2|η1+η1+|,˜ρˆn1a2M1+=αpα|s(α)2M1+|2|η2M1+η2M1+|,˜ρˆn1a2M1=αpα|s(α)2M1|2|η2M1η2M1|,˜ρˆn1a1=αpα|s(α)1|2|η1η1|,˜ρˆn2a1+=αpα|t(α)1+|2|ε1+ε1+|,˜ρˆn2a2M1+=αpα|t(α)2M1+|2|ε2M1+ε2M1+|,˜ρˆn2a2M1=αpα|t(α)2M1|2|ε2M1ε2M1|,˜ρˆn2a1=αpα|t(α)1|2|ε1ε1|.(31)

    Suppose Bob’s states have an LHS description, they must satisfy Eqs. (5) and (6). Then, Bob will check the following set of 2M+1 equations :

    ρ̃an̂k=ξ(a|n̂k,ξ)ξρξ.(32)
    If these 2M+1 equations have a contradiction, that is they cannot have a common solution for the sets {ξρξ} and (a|n̂k,ξ), then Bob is convinced that the LHS models are non-existent and that Alice can steer the state of his qubits.

    In the quantum result, there are 2M+1 pure states in Eq. (31). Then in the LHS description, it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 2M+1. It is a fact that a density matrix of pure state can only be expanded by itself. Therefore, any ρ̃an̂k in Eq. (32) contains only one term. So for the LHS models results, we have

    ρ̃a1+n̂1=1ρ1,ρ̃a2M1+n̂1=2M1ρ2M1,ρ̃a2M1n̂1=2M1+1ρ2M1+1,ρ̃a1n̂1=2Mρ2M,ρ̃a1+n̂2=2M+1ρ2M+1,ρ̃a2M1+n̂2=2M+2M1ρ2M+2M1,ρ̃a2M1n̂2=2M+2M1+1ρ2M+2M1+1,ρ̃a1n̂2=2M+1ρ2M+1.(33)
    Finally, we sum up terms in Eq. (33) and take the trace. The left side gives tr(ρ̃n̂1+ρ̃n̂2)=2tr(ρB)=2, the result of quantum. While the right side gives tr(1ρ1++2M+1ρ2M+1)=tr(ρB)=1, the result of the classical LHS models. This leads to the contradiction2=1”, which represents the EPR paradox in the 2-setting steering protocol. □

    Remark 1. For 2-qubit pure state Eq. (2), Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are always pure. So we only need to verify whether it satisfies the measurement requirement. It can be seen that in the 2-setting protocol {,x̂}, Bob’s results are {|00|,|11|} and {|++|,||}, respectively.19 Obviously, this satisfies the measurement requirement. According to our analysis, such state equation (2) can get the contradiction “2=1”.

    Remark 2. For the 4-qubit mixed state Eq. (12), it is necessary to analyze whether it satisfies both the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement. In the 2-setting protocol {n̂1,n̂2}={,ŷx̂}, Bob’s eight conditional states are all pure states as shown in Eq. (16). For two different measurements Pan̂1 and Pan̂2, Bob’s results are different. It is obvious that the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied at the same time, so the specific 4-qubit mixed state equation (12) can also get the contradiction “2=1”.

    In the EPR steering paradox, we propose a theorem for N-qubit quantum states which contains two requirements: the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement. If Alice and Bob share an N-qubit mixed state, there will be a contradiction of “2=1” only when the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement are satisfied at the same time. If they share an N-qubit pure state, the pure state requirement is automatically satisfied. In this situation, after Alice’s measurement, Bob must get a pure state, which only needs to meet the measurement requirement. Our results are completely consistent with the previous conclusions. This confirms the correctness of our conclusion.

    3. Bell-Like Basis Measurement

    Here we show a more specific example of the Bell-like basis measurement for the N-qubit mixed states. Let us consider Alice and Bob share an N-qubit entangled state ρAB=αpα|ψAB(α)ψAB(α)|, in which |ψAB(α) may be written as

    |ψAB(α)=i(si+(α)|+ϕi|ηi+(α)+si(α)|ϕi|ηi(α))(34)
    and i(|si+(α)|2+|si(α)|2)=1. Alice has M(M<N) particles and Bob has (NM) particles. In particular, in the 2-setting steering protocol {n̂1,n̂2} (with n̂1n̂2), Alice performs the Bell-like basis measurement on her qubits. Then according to the theorem, we analyze whether this example can obtain the contradiction “2=1”, and if yes, what conditions ρAB need to meet with the Bell-like basis measurement.

    The Bell-like basis measurement can be written as

    Pa1+n̂k=(cosβk|+ϕ1+sinβk|ϕ1)(cosβk+ϕ1|+sinβkϕ1|),Pa2M1+n̂k=(cosβk|+ϕ2M1+sinβk|ϕ2M1)(cosβk+ϕ2M1|+sinβkϕ2M1|),Pa2M1n̂k=(sinβk|+ϕ2M1cosβk|ϕ2M1)(sinβk+ϕ2M1|cosβkϕ2M1|),Pa1n̂k=(sinβk|+ϕ1cosβk|ϕ1)(sinβk+ϕ1|cosβkϕ1|),(35)
    in which βk[0,2π). Alice performs the measurement along n̂k directions (with k=1,2). And |±ϕi (i=1,2,,2M1) is a set of complete basis of 2M-dimensional Hilbert space. We prove that in Appendix C. After Alice’s measurement, Bob obtains
    ρ̃ai+n̂k=αpα|ωi+k(α)ωi+k(α)|,ρ̃ain̂k=αpα|ωik(α)ωik(α)|,(36)
    with
    |ωi+k(α)=si+(α)cosβk|ηi+(α)+si(α)sinβk|ηi(α),|ωik(α)=si+(α)sinβk|ηi+(α)si(α)cosβk|ηi(α).(37)

    First, in Bell-like basis measurement, the transformation matrix {V(j±)(i±)} is

    V=cos(β1β2)0sin(β1β2)00cos(β1β2)0sin(β1β2)sin(β1β2)0cos(β1β2)00sin(β1β2)0cos(β1β2).(38)
    It is obvious that there are only two nonzero matrix elements Vjq+ as well as Vjq (with q=1,2,,2M1) in each row of matrix {V(j±)(i±)}, and |χj±(α) contains only two terms. Similarly, only |ηq+(α) and |ηq(α) contribute to |ψAB(α), and we can consider |ψAB(α) as
    |ψAB(α)=sq+(α)|+ϕq|ηq+(α)+sq(α)|ϕq|ηq(α).(39)
    The measurement requirement also requires
    |ψAB(α)i(si+(α)|+ϕi+si(α)|ϕi)|η(α),
    so |ηq+(α)|ηq(α). In this way, the measurement requirement is satisfied. Second, the pure state requirement requires that |ηq±(α) is independent of α, i.e.
    |ψAB(α)=sq+(α)|+ϕq|ηq++sq(α)|ϕq|ηq.(40)

    It is apparent that after a series of analysis, the form of |ψAB(α) is simple and only contains two terms. There is an interesting question worthy of our further analysis, that is, whether |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) can contain the same states? Suppose that |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) are

    |ψAB(α)=sp+(α)|+ϕp|ηp++sp(α)|ϕp|ηp,|ψAB(α)=sp+(α)|+ϕp|ηp++sp(α)|ϕp|ηp,(41)
    with p{1,2,,2m}. The pure state requirement requires
    sp+(α)=cα(p+)αsp+(α),sp(α)=cα(p)αsp(α)(42)
    and
    Vjp+sp+(α)|ηp++Vjpsip(α)|ηp=dαjα(Vjp+sp+(α)|ηp++Vjpsp(α)|ηp).(43)
    The measurement requirement requires |ηp+(α)|ηp(α). According to Eqs. (42) and (43), we have
    cα(p+)α=cα(p)α=1dαjαcαα.(44)
    So
    |ψAB(α)=cαα|ψAB(α),(45)
    that means |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) are the same state. In summary, |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) cannot contain the same state.

    Therefore, for arbitrary α and α, we have

    |ψAB(α)=sq+(α)|+ϕq|ηq++sq(α)|ϕq|ηq,|ψAB(α)=sq+(α)|+ϕq|ηq++sq(α)|ϕq|ηq,(46)
    with qq and q,q=1,2,,2M1. After Alice’s measurement, Bob’s results are
    ρ̃aq+n̂k=pα|ωq+k(α)ωq+k(α)|,ρ̃aqn̂k=pα|ωqk(α)ωqk(α)|.(47)
    Similarly, suppose every Bob’s state has a LHS description. Bob can check the following set of 2M+1 equations :
    ρ̃a1+n̂k=ξ(a1+|n̂k,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a2M1+n̂k=ξ(a2M1+|n̂k,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a1n̂k=ξ(a1|n̂k,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a2M1n̂k=ξ(a2M1|n̂k,ξ)ξρξ.(48)
    According to Eq. (47), Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are pure. A density matrix of pure state can only be expanded by itself, therefore, from Eq. (47) we have
    ρ̃a1+n̂k=1ρ1,ρ̃a2M1+n̂k=2M1ρ2M1,ρ̃a1n̂k=2M1+1ρ2M1+1,ρ̃a2M1n̂k=2Mρ2M.k=1,2(49)
    By summing them up and taking the trace, the left side gives tr(ρ̃n̂1+ρ̃n̂2)=2tr(ρB)=2. But the right side gives tr(1ρ1++2M+1ρ2M+1)=tr(ρB)=1. This leads to the contradiction “2=1

    In summary, we discuss the steering paradox with the Bell-like basis measurement. It shows that for Bell-like basis measurement, when ρAB satisfied both the pure state requirement and the measurement requirement, we can obtain the contradiction “2=1”. In this case, |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) cannot contain the same state, and only contain two items. It is evident that the maximum value range of α is from 1 to 2M1 (M is the number of particles of Alice), that is, the maximum rank of ρAB is 2M1 for the Bell-like basis measurement.

    4. Nonexistence of Contradiction “2=1” for 2-Qubit Mixed States

    In this section, we apply the results to the 2-qubit mixed states. We get the following corollary.

    Corollary 1. If Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit mixed state, there is no contradiction2=1”.

    From the above analysis, we know that for the Bell-like basis measurement, the maximum rank of ρAB is 2M1. Suppose Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit entangled state ρAB and each of them has a qubit, then M=1. If Alice performs the Bell-like basis measurement, the maximum rank of ρAB is 1. That is, for 2-qubit entangled states with the Bell-like basis measurement, only the 2-qubit prue entangled states have the contradiction “2=1”. So is there a contradiction “2=1” for 2-qubit mixed states? Next, we prove that there is no contradiction “2=1” for 2-qubit mixed states

    Proof. Suppose Alice and Bob share a 2-qubit mixed state ρAB=αpα|ψAB(α)ψAB(α)|, in which

    |ψAB(α)=s1(α)|ϕ1|η1+s2(α)|ϕ2|η2.(50)
    Here we take |η1(α)=|η1 and |η2(α)=|η2 to satisfy the pure state requirement. The measurement requirement requests s1(α),s2(α)0, and |η1|η2. Alice takes one particle and the other belongs to Bob. Similarly, in the 2-setting steering protocol {n̂1,n̂2}, suppose that Alice’s projective measurements are {|ϕiϕi|} and {|φjφj|}, where |ϕi|φj|<1 and i,j=1,2. Then Bob’s unnormalized conditional states are
    ρ̃ain̂1=αpα|si(α)|2|ηiηi|,ρ̃ajn̂2=αpα|χj(α)χj(α)|,(51)
    where |χj(α)=iVjisi(α)|ηi(α), Vji=φj|ϕi. In order to get the contradiction, for any α and α, the conditional state of Bob needs to satisfy
    |χj(α)=dαjα|χj(α),si(α)=cαiαsi(α).(52)
    According to Eq. (52), we have cα(i)α=cα(i)α=1dαjα. Then we can obtain |ψAB(α) and |ψAB(α) are the same state, similarly. Therefore, there is no contradiction “2=1” in 2-qubit mixed states. □

    5. Conclusion

    We have presented a simple EPR steering paradox that shows the incompatibility of the local-hidden-state models with quantum theory for any N-qubit entangled state based on a 2-setting steering protocol. The argument is valid for any N-qubit entangled state, not only N-qubit pure entangled states, but more importantly, N-qubit mixed entangled states. We propose a simple theorem and prove that for any N-qubit state satisfying simultaneously “the pure state requirement” and “the measurement requirement”, then the contradiction “2=1” can be obtained. In the example of Bell-like basis measurement, we obtain that the maximum rank of the N-qubit mixed state is 2M1 (M is the number of particles of Alice), and prove that there is no contradiction “2=1” in the 2-qubit mixed state. In general, we obtain the contradiction “2=1” in a more general case. Furthermore, if one considers the EPR steering scenario in k-setting for arbitrary N-qudit entangled mixed state, then following the similar approach, one can arrive at a full contradiction, i.e. “k=1”.

    Acknowledgments

    J.L.C. is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant Nos. 12275136 and 12075001) and the 111 Project of B23045. H.X.M. is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant No. 11901317). Z.J.L. is supported by the Nankai Zhide Foundation.

    ORCID

    Zhi-Jie Liu  https://orcid.org/0009-0008-0373-1796

    Jie Zhou  https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7518-3716

    Hui-Xian Meng  https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3807-7201

    Xing-Yan Fan  https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0702-4094

    Mi Xie  https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2482-121X

    Fu-Lin Zhang  https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7077-1001

    Jing-Ling Chen  https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3411-6015

    Appendix A. Can Bob Have the Same State in the Same Measurement?

    In order to obtain the contradiction “2=1”, we analyze whether Bob can have the same pure state in the same measurement, and whether Bob can have the same pure state in different measurements.

    After Alice’s measurement, Bob obtains

    ρ̃a1+n̂1=αpα|s1+(α)|2|η1+η1+|,ρ̃am+n̂1=αpα|sm+(α)|2|ηm+ηm+|,ρ̃an+n̂1=αpα|sn+(α)|2|ηn+ηn+|,ρ̃a2M1+n̂1=αpα|s2M1+(α)|2|η2M1+η2M1+|,ρ̃a2M1n̂1=αpα|s2M1(α)|2|η2M1η2M1|,ρ̃ann̂1=αpα|sn(α)|2|ηnηn|,ρ̃amn̂1=αpα|sm(α)|2|ηmηm|,ρ̃a1n̂1=αpα|s1(α)|2|η1η1|,ρ̃a1+n̂2=αpα|t1+(α)|2|ε1+ε1+|,ρ̃am+n̂2=αpα|tm+(α)|2|εm+εm+|,ρ̃an+n̂2=αpα|tn+(α)|2|εn+εn+|,ρ̃a2M1+n̂2=αpα|t2M1+(α)|2|ε2M1+ε2M1+|,ρ̃a2M1n̂2=αpα|t2M1(α)|2|ε2M1ε2M1|,ρ̃ann̂2=αpα|tn(α)|2|εnεn|,ρ̃amn̂2=αpα|tm(α)|2|εmεm|,ρ̃a1n̂2=αpα|t1(α)|2|ε1ε1|.(A.1)

    In Eq. (A.1), assuming that |ηm+=|ηn+, i.e. only 2M+11 different pure states appear in the quantum result of Eq. (A.1), so that it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 2M+11, namely, one can take the ensemble as

    {ξρξ}={1ρ1,2ρ2,3ρ3,,2M+11ρ2M+11}.(A.2)
    Then Eq. (A.1) can be written as
    ρ̃a1+n̂1=ξ=12M+11(a1+|n̂1,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃am+n̂1=ξ=12M+11(am+|n̂1,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃an+n̂1=ξ=12M+11(an+|n̂1,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a1n̂1=ξ=12M+11(a1|n̂1,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a1+n̂2=ξ=12M+11(a1+|n̂2,ξ)ξρξ,ρ̃a1n̂2=ξ=12M+11(a1|n̂2,ξ)ξρξ.(A.3)
    Since the 2M+1 states on the left-hand side of Eq. (A.1) are all pure states, a pure state cannot be obtained by a convex sum of other different states. Therefore,
    ρ̃a1+n̂1=(a1+|n̂1,1)1ρ1,(a1+|n̂1,2)=(a1+|n̂1,3)==(a1+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(A.4)
    Similarly, one has
    ρ̃a2+n̂1=(a2+|n̂1,2)2ρ2,(a2+|n̂1,1)=(a2+|n̂1,3)==(a2+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(A.5)

    ρ̃am+n̂1=(am+|n̂1,m)mρm,(am+|n̂1,1)=(am+|n̂1,2)==(am+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(A.6)

    ρ̃an+n̂1=(an+|n̂1,m)mρm,(an+|n̂1,1)=(an+|n̂1,2)==(an+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(A.7)

    ρ̃a1n̂1=(a1|n̂1,2M1)2M1ρ2M1,(a2M|n̂1,1)=(a2M|n̂1,2)==(a2M|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(A.8)
    ρ̃a1+n̂2=(a1+|n̂2,1)2Mρ2M,(a1+|n̂2,2)=(a1+|n̂2,3)==(a1+|n̂2,2M+11)=0.(A.9)

    ρ̃a1n̂2=(a1|n̂2,2M+11)2M+11ρ2M+11,(a1|n̂2,1)=(a1|n̂2,2)==(a1|n̂2,2M+12)=0.(A.10)

    Because a(a|n̂,ξ)=1, one has

    ρ̃a1+n̂1=1ρ1,ρ̃am+n̂1=(am+|n̂1,m)mρm,ρ̃an+n̂1=(an+|n̂1,n)nρn,ρ̃a1n̂1=2M1ρ2M1,ρ̃a1+n̂2=2Mρ2M,ρ̃a1n̂2=2M+11ρ2M+11.(A.11)
    where (am+|n̂1,m)+(an+|n̂1,n)=1. The sum on the left-hand side of Eq. (A.11) is 2ρB, and the sum on the right-hand side is ρB. By summing terms in Eq. (A.11) and taking trace, we arrive at the contradiction “2=1”. So in the same measurement, if Bob gets the same pure state, we can get the contradiction “2=1”.

    Appendix B. Can Bob Have the Same State in Different Measurements?

    In Eq. (A.1), assuming that |ηm+=|εm+, i.e. only 2M+11 different pure states appear in the quantum result of Eq. (A.1). Similarly, it is sufficient to take ξ from 1 to 2M+11, one can take the ensemble as Eq. (A.2). Then one has Eq. (A.3). The 2M+1 states on the left-hand side of Eq. (A.1) are all pure states. The same reasoning can be used to obtain

    ρ̃a1+n̂1=(a1+|n̂1,1)1ρ1,(a1+|n̂1,2)=(a1+|n̂1,3)==(a1+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(B.1)
    Similarly, one has
    ρ̃a2+n̂1=(a2+|n̂1,2)2ρ2,(a2+|n̂1,1)=(a2+|n̂1,3)==(a2+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(B.2)

    ρ̃am+n̂1=(am+|n̂1,m)mρm,(am+|n̂1,1)=(am+|n̂1,2)==(am+|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(B.3)

    ρ̃a1n̂1=(a1|n̂1,2M)2Mρ2M,(a2M|n̂1,1)=(a2M|n̂1,2)==(a2M|n̂1,2M+11)=0.(B.4)
    ρ̃a1+n̂2=(a1+|n̂2,1)2M+1ρ2M+1,(a1+|n̂2,2)=(a1+|n̂2,3)==(a1+|n̂2,2M+11)=0.(B.5)

    ρ̃am+n̂2=(am+|n̂2,m)2M+mρ2M+m,(a1|n̂2,1)=(a1|n̂2,2)==(a1|n̂2,2M+11)=0.(B.6)

    ρ̃a1n̂2=(a1|n̂2,2M+11)2M+11ρ2M+11,(a1|n̂2,1)=(a1|n̂2,2)==(a1|n̂2,2M+12)=0.(B.7)

    Because a(a|n̂,ξ)=1, one has

    ρ̃a1n̂1=1ρ1,ρ̃am+n̂1=mρm,ρ̃a1n̂1=2Mρ2M,ρ̃a1+n̂2=2M+1ρ2M+1,ρ̃am+n̂2=2M+mρ2M+m,ρ̃a1n̂2=2M+11ρ2M+11.(B.8)
    Here (am+|n̂1,m)=1, (am+|n̂2,m)=1, no more (am+|n̂1,m)+(am+|n̂2,m)=1. The sum on the left-hand side of Eq. (B.8) is 2ρB, and the sum on the right-hand side is ρB+iρi. By summing terms in Eq. (B.8) and taking trace, we no longer get the contradiction “2=1”. So in the different measurements, if Bob gets the same pure state, we cannot get the contradiction “2=1”.

    Appendix C. |±ϕi is a Set of Complete Basis of Hilbert Space

    Here we show that |±ϕi (i=1,2,,2M1) which in the Bell-like basis measurement is a set of complete basis of 2M-dimensional Hilbert space. For any k(k=1,2), we have i=12M1(Pai+n̂k+Pain̂k)=1. That can be expanded as

    i=12M1(Pai+n̂k+Pain̂k)=i=12M1(cos2βk|+ϕi+ϕi|+cosβksinβk|+ϕiϕi|+sinβkcosβk|ϕi+ϕi|+sin2βk|ϕiϕi|+sin2βk|+ϕi+ϕi|sinβkcosβk|+ϕiϕi|cosβksinβk|ϕi+ϕi|+cos2βk|ϕiϕi|)=i=12M1(|+ϕi+ϕi|+|ϕiϕi|)=𝟙.(C.1)
    It is obvious that |±ϕi is a set of complete basis of 2M-dimensional Hilbert space.