![]() |
This invaluable book is a collection of 31 important — both in ideas and results — papers published by mathematical logicians in the 20th Century. The papers have been selected by Professor Gerald E Sacks. Some of the authors are Gödel, Kleene, Tarski, A Robinson, Kreisel, Cohen, Morley, Shelah, Hrushovski and Woodin.
Sample Chapter(s)
Chapter 1: The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis (364 KB)
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_fmatter
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0001
This is the first of two notes in which we outline a proof of the fact that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be derived from the other axioms of set theory, including the Axiom of Choice. Since Gödel3 has shown that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with these axioms, the independence of the hypothesis is thus established. We shall work with the usual axioms for Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory,2 and by Z-F we shall denote these axioms without the Axiom of Choice, (but with the Axiom of Regularity). By a model for Z-F we shall always mean a collection of actual sets with the usual ε-relation satisfying Z-F. We use the standard definitions3 for the set of integers ω, ordinal, and cardinal numbers…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0002
This paper is a continuation of reference 1, in which we began a proof of the fact that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be derived from the other axioms of set theory, including the Axiom of Choice. We use the same notation as employed in reference 1.
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0003
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0004
In this paper we shall prove three theorems about recursively enumerable sets. The first two answer questions posed by Myhill [1].
The three proofs are independent and can be presented in any order. Certain notations will be common to all three. We shall denote by “Re” the set enumerated by the procedure of which e is the Gödel number. In describing the construction for each proof, we shall suppose that a clerk is carrying out the simultaneous enumeration of R0, R1, R2,…, in such a way that at each step only a finite number of sets have begun to be enumerated and only a finite number of the members of any set have been listed. (One plan the clerk can follow is to turn his attention at Step a to the enumeration of Re where e + 1 is the number of prime factors of a. Then each Re receives his attention infinitely often.) We shall denote by “Rea” the set of numbers which, at or before Step a, the clerk has listed as members of Re. Obviously, all the Rea are finite sets, recursive uniformly in e and a. For any a we can determine effectively the highest e for which Rea is not empty, and for any a, e we can effectively find the highest member of Rea, just by scanning what the clerk has done by Step a. Additional notations will be introduced in the proofs to which they pertain.
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0005
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0006
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0007
If M is an arbitrary domain of things in which a binary relation ε is defined, call “propositional function over M” any expression φ containing (besides brackets) only the following symbols: 1. Variables x, y …. whose range is M. 2. Symbols a1 … an denoting2 individual elements of M (referred to in the sequel as “the constants of φ”). 3. ε. 4. ∼ (not), ∨ (or). 5. Quantifiers for the above variables x, y …* Denote by M′ the set of all subsets of M defined by prop. funct. φ(x) over M. Call a function f with s variables a “function in M” if for any elements x1 … xs of Mf(x1 … xs) is defined and is an element of M…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0008
We give a proof of the geometric Mordell-Lang conjecture, in any characteristic. Our method involves a model-theoretic analysis of the kernel of Manin's homomorphism and of a certain analog in characteristic p.
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0009
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0010
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0011
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0012
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0013
Hilbert's tenth problem has the following formulation (cf. [1]):
Specify a procedure which in a finite number of steps enables one to determine whether or not a given diophantine equation with an arbitrary number of indeterminates and with rational integer coefficients has a solution in rational integers…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0014
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0015
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0016
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0017
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0018
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0019
Our main result is: if b and c are recursively enumerable degrees such that b < c, then there exists a recursively enumerable degree d such that b < d < c. By degree we mean degree of recursive unsolvability as denned by Kleene and Post [2]. A degree is called recursively enumerable if it is the degree of a recursively enumerable set. The upper semi-lattice of recursively enumerable degrees has a least member, 0, the degree of all recursive sets, and a greatest member, 0′, the degree of all complete sets. Post [4] asked: does there exist a recursively enumerable degree d such that 0 < d < 0′? Friedberg [1] and Muchnik [3] answered Post's question in the affirmative. Sacks [5] showed that every countable, partially ordered set is imbeddable in the upper semi-lattice of recursively enumerable degrees. Muchnik [3] announced that if c is a non-zero, recursively enumerable degree, then there exists a recursively enumerable degree d such that 0 < d < c…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0020
A cardinal number m will be called measurable if and only if there is a set X of cardinality m and a non-trivial, real-valued, countably additive measure μ defined on all subsets of X. (The term non-trivial can be taken to mean that μ(X) = 1 and μ({x}) = 0, for all χ ɛ X). If 2ℵ0 = ℵ1, Banach and Kuratowski [1] proved that ℵ1 is not measurable. Ulam [12] proved that if there is a measurable cardinal, then either 2ℵ0 is measurable or there exists a 2-valued measurable cardinal (2-valued in the sense that the measure μ can be assumed to take on only the values 0 and 1). Ulam and Tarski showed that no cardinal less than the first strengly inaccessible cardinal beyond ℵ0 can be 2-valued measurable (cf. [12], esp. footnote 1, p. 146). Last year, using some new results of Hanf, Tarski proved [11] that many inaccessibles, in particular the first beyend ℵ0, are not 2-valued measurable (for other proofs cf. [6] and [2]). Even though the least 2-valued measurable cardinal, if it exists at all, now appears to be incredibly large since Tarski's results apply to a seemingly inexhaustible number of inaccessible cardinals, it still seems plausible to many people including the author to assume that such cardinals do exist. However, this assumption has some surprising consequences, for, as shall be outlined below, we can show that the existence of measurable cardinals contradiets Gödel's axiom of constructibility…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0021
We study KT(λ) = sup{| S(A) | : | A | ≦ λ} and extend some results for totally transcendental theroies to the case of stable theories. We then investigate categoricity of elementary and pseudo-elementary classes.
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0022
One of the principal objectives of the foundations of mathematics is to “explain”, as far as possible, the basic concepts of mathematics. In the simplest case, concepts are explained in terms of other concepts. Thus the concept of rational number is explained in terms of the simpler concepts of integer and ordered pair. The object is not to reduce all problems about rational numbers to problems about integers and ordered pairs, but to be able to say that we understand the notion of a rational number as fully as we understand the notions of integer and ordered pair…
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0023
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0024
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0025
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0026
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0027
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0028
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0029
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0030
It is shown that if there exists a supercompact cardinal then every set of reals, which is an element of L(ℝ), is the projection of a weakly homogeneous tree. As a consequence of this theorem and recent work of Martin and Steel [Martin, D. A. & Steel, J. R. (1988) Proc. Nail. Acad. Sci. USA 85, 6582–6586], it follows that (if there is a supercompact cardinal) every set of reals in L(ℝ) is determined.
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_0031
The following sections are included:
https://doi.org/10.1142/9789812564894_bmatter
The following sections are included:
Sample Chapter(s)
Chapter 1: The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis (364k)